Exploitation

(EPE, pp 307-310)

In a sense, "taking advantage of" or "using selfishly" other people is precisely the sort of behavior assumed to be the norm by mainstream neo-classical economics. There, market transactors are seen as forthrightly using <each other> in pure, unabashed self-interest, and odious as this universalized self-seeking may seem, no one is harmed by it, at least not in competitive markets, where an 'invisible hand' is said to turn it to the best interest of all.

Heterodox political economists, however, understand "exploitation" quite differently. Some would argue that not only is self-oriented utility-maximization immoral, even in ideal circumstances [see ETHICS, MORAL SCIENCE & POLITICAL ECONOMY], but it is also contrary to RATIONALITY, being antithetical to the survival needs of a highly social human species. Moreover, as heterodox economists use the term, "exploitation" designates a fundamentally <unbalanced> relationship: The "exploiter" has some form of POWER over the other person -- perhaps based on a threat of physical or emotional abuse, or fraud or other deception -- and uses it to get the other person to do things that are not in his/her own interest but in the exploiter's interest instead. The 'subordinate' may or may not be aware that some of his/her time or energy is being diverted for someone else's use, but in either case would not consent to it if permitted some voice in the matter.

Thus, exploitation means taking for one's own advantage some of the very 'life-activity' of another person [see ALIENATION], or getting the other person to <labor> for oneself rather than for his/her own purposes. Most mainstream economists would doubt that exploitation so defined exists in any great degree in free-market systems, although they do acknowledge that firms with ECONOMIC POWER due to imperfect MARKET STRUCTURES may "exploit" their customers or employees. Heterodox economists, however, are committed to investigating several varieties of exploitation, and find them pervasive, and even systemic, in the capitalist economy just as they are elsewhere: social CLASS, in which subordinate class members labor for a dominant class by virtue of a lack of access to the society's means of production; RACIAL exploitation, in which members of one racial or ethnic group are similarly compelled to labor for another; PATRIARCHY, where women and perhaps children are exploited by men; and COLONIALISM AND IMPERIALISM, in which people of one society or nation are exploited by those of another.

Of these, probably the best understood among economists is class-based exploitation -- its analysis is in many ways a model for that of the other forms, and some would even subsume the latter as mere special cases of it [see RACE, ETHNICITY, GENDER, CLASS]. A dominant class compels or induces a working class to produce a SURPLUS of goods and services, i.e., above and beyond what working class people themselves need for 'subsistence'. The surplus is appropriated by the dominant class, hence represents the product of a portion of workers' labor that they have expended not for themselves but for the dominant class. Because some kind of power structure is necessarily involved, part of the surplus must go to sustaining that structure -- e.g., for the subsistence and other material needs of people in the 'command hierarchy', in police and adjudication institutions, in ideological activities, etc. [see PRODUCTIVE & UNPRODUCTIVE LABOR & CAPITAL]. The rest of the surplus is then available to the dominant class for personal or collective consumption or for investment.

In principle, it is possible to measure the 'extent' or the <rate of exploitation> in a class society -- e.g., by the amount of labor time workers spend producing the surplus, relative to that spent on the 'necessary' portion of their product [Marx, 1977]. So measured, the 'extent' of exploitation may be increased, cet. par., by increasing the HOURS OF WORK per day (or per year, etc.) or the intensity with which workers labor, by increasing the PRODUCTIVITY of labor, or by reducing workers' material livelihood. In the last case, in principle, the rate of exploitation may be so greatly increased that the working class is <superexploited>, i.e, the workers' portion of their total product is reduced to something less than they require for subsistence [Mandel, 1970, 455]. Of course, such a circumstance cannot last for long. And too, increasing the rate of exploitation by these or other means might require a greater expenditure on strengthening the requisite power structure than may be warranted by the additional surplus returned to the dominant class. In general then, the rate of exploitation in a society at a point in time is determined by the whole complexity of factors underlying both the productivity of labor and the balance of the 'class struggle' [see CLASS PROCESSES, POSITIONS & STRUCTURES]. Besides thus indicating the state of an important set of social relations, the rate of exploitation is a crucial determinant of an economy's capacity for growth [see SURPLUS APPROACH TO DEVELOPMENT], and particularly in capitalist economies, of the RATE OF PROFIT as well.

Obviously SLAVERY and FEUDALISM are examples of class-based exploitation, and nearly all western political economists would agree that so too are modern Soviet-type COMMUNIST economies. Despite neo-classical economists' generally disregarding the claim, CAPITALISM is arguably an economy of class-based exploitation as well: Property income, the hallmark of capitalism, is not a 'reward for productive work' but instead a share of the economy's total product received solely as a function of property ownership [see SURPLUS VALUE AS PROFIT, RENT & INTEREST] -- and access to it is, of course, inherently highly unequal [see INEQUALITY OF INCOME, WEALTH & POWER].

Racial exploitation, patriarchy and imperialism are closely connected with the phenomenon of social class. Classes have often been partly defined along lines of gender and/or 'foreign-ness', and all these forms of exploitation probably arose together and reinforced each other in the pre-history of human 'civilization' [see ECONOMIC ANTHROPOLOGY]. Today, however, these modes of exploitation are considerably differentiated.

Men's exploitation of women rests mainly upon unequal access to means of economic and personal enrichment and positions of status and influence, even in the most advanced societies today, on account of legal, cultural and other institutional DISCRIMINATION. In the paid labor-force a SEXUAL DIVISION OF LABOR -- arising from women's socialization in youth, school 'tracking', etc. -- places women disproportionately in subordinate and low-wage occupations. On account of such inequalities in the larger society, power relations arise within the HOUSEHOLD, where they engender, in turn, an 'unequal exchange' of DOMESTIC LABOR between men and women. Violence may also play a role in subduing women in the household, and their inferior position there then reinforces their disadvantaged status in the larger society, by permitting them to be more easily exploited in the paid labor-force. Lower wages for women than for men follow directly, even in the same occupations, women being thereby subject to a higher rate of exploitation in wage-labor -- which, of course, reinforces the adverse power relations and exploitation to which they are subject within the family.

Similar processes are at work in racial and ethnic exploitation. Legal and extra-legal discrimination places ethnic groups in disadvantaged positions in external and INTERNAL LABOR MARKETS, housing markets, schooling, etc. This leads to major disparities in their and their offspring's accumulated wealth and cultural and HUMAN CAPITAL, which in turn reinforces their segregation into subordinate and low-paying occupations, and strengthens attitudes and practices of RACISM toward them among more privileged groups. While many would contend that capitalism per se has nothing to do with race and gender exploitation, clearly it is arguable that it has historically intensified rather than mitigated both forms.

Capitalism is also implicated in the modern history of colonial expansionism [see PRIMITIVE ACCUMULATION]. In general, exploitation in colonialism occurs by overtly coercive means: the colonizer simply takes the colony's products and resources without pretense of offering anything in exchange. In imperialism, at least that of the late twentieth century, the means of exploitation are much more complex. One country may subtly apply political and military power to dominate the other country's TRADE POLICY and other policies on financial and investment flows, EXCHANGE RATES, taxes, labor relations, etc. [see CORE-PERIPHERY ANALYSIS]. Or it may merely take advantage of an industrially undeveloped country's inherently retarded position in competitive world markets [see COMPARATIVE ADVANTAGE AND UNEQUAL EXCHANGE]. In either case, the outcome is a retardation or reversal in the subordinate country's development due to the appropriation of its economic surplus by the dominant country (and perhaps the latter's allied 'comprador' classes in the subordinate country) [see UNEVEN DEVELOPMENT, LAW OF].

Exploitation is invariably rationalized by those benefitting from it [see IDEOLOGY & POLITICAL ECONOMY]. For example, dominant classes may argue that economic development requires a surplus product for investment, and class-based exploitation (especially the capitalist kind) is the most effective means of appropriating one. Of course, it must still be shown that those in the working class (or perhaps their offspring) will themselves benefit from the growth process -- and that, most importantly, they <consent> to it. Alternatively, the dominant groups may argue that they 'deserve' their status in one way or another -- subordinates are, for example, 'innately inferior'. The analysis of exploitation shows quite clearly, however, that the disadvantaged are in that position not on account of any 'inferiority' at all, but by having been <subjugated to others' advantage>. Progress toward a congenial human society can only begin by acknowledging that fact.

REFERENCES & FURTHER READINGS:

Barone, Charles (1985). Marxist Thought on Imperialism. M.E. Sharpe: Armonk, N.Y.

Mandel, Ernest (1970). Marxist Economic Theory. Monthly Review Press: N.Y.

Marx, Karl (1977). Capital (Vol. 1). Vintage Books, Random House: N.Y.

Roemer, John E. (1988). Free to Lose. Harvard U. Press: Cambridge.

Walby, S. (1990). Theorizing Patriarchy. Blackwell: Oxford.

           Back to "Encyclopedia" page.